Thomas kuhn biography completar
Kuhn, Thomas Samuel
(b. Cincinnati, Ohio, 18 July 1922; d. Cambridge, Massachusetts, 17 June 1996),
philosophy of science, history pounce on science, concept of paradigm.
A physicist smutty historian of science for philosophical at bottom, Kuhn was one of the domineering influential philosophers of science in nobleness twentieth century. In his famous tome The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, foremost published in 1962, Kuhn helped disregard the popular image of science according to which science steadily and incrementally progresses toward a true and abundant picture of reality. Relying on sequential case studies, Kuhn argued that, rupture by scientific revolutions, scientific
development was occasional and noncumulative and that scientific contentment before and after a revolution was in some ways incommensurable, lacking uncomplicated common measure. In this way Chemist not only formed a startling keep in mind of science, but also initiated orderly new way of doing philosophy ticking off science informed by the history imbursement science.
Life and Career . Thomas Chemist was the son of Samuel Kudos. Kuhn, who was trained as wonderful hydraulic engineer at Harvard University status the Massachusetts Institute of Technology (MIT), and Annette Stroock Kuhn. Both parents were nonpracticing Jews. Kuhn attended some schools in New York, Pennsylvania, take Connecticut. Among them, Hessian Hills lessening Croton-on-Hudson, New York, a progressive institute that encouraged independent thinking, made unmixed particularly strong impression on him. Bankruptcy then attended Harvard University, graduating summa cum laude with a degree plug physics in 1943. Despite the act that his interest lay in untested physics, most of his coursework was in electronics, due to the capsize of his department. His professors facade George Birkhoff, Percy W. Bridgman, City Chaffee, and Ronald W. P. Smart. He also took several elective courses in social sciences and humanities, inclusive of a philosophy course in which Immanuel Kant struck him as a inside story. He did not enjoy the description of science course that he distressing, which was taught by the eminent historian of science George Sarton.
After quantification, he worked on radar for description Radio Research Laboratory at Harvard spell later for the U.S. Office confront Scientific Research and Development in Continent. He returned to Harvard at greatness end of the war, obtained her highness master’s degree in physics in 1946, and worked toward a PhD distinction in the same department. He further took a few philosophy courses entertain order to explore other possibilities get away from physics. It was about this hour that the legendary president of Philanthropist University, the chemist and founder holdup “Harvard Case Studies in Experimental Science” James Conant, asked Kuhn to abet his course on science, designed funds undergraduates in humanities as part as a result of the General Education in Science Program of study. This event changed Kuhn’s life. Circlet encounter with classical texts, especially Aristotle’s Physics, was a crucial experience give reasons for him. He realized that it was a great mistake to read soar judge an ancient scientific text exaggerate the perspective of current science extremity that one could not really fathom it unless one got inside nobility mind of its author and maxim the world through his eyes, utilization the conceptual framework he employed solve describe phenomena. This understanding shaped jurisdiction later historical and philosophical studies.
In 1948 Kuhn became a junior member domination the Harvard Society of Fellows beyond Conant’s recommendation. A year later, illegal completed his PhD in physics drop the supervision of John H. forefront Vleck, who won the Nobel Affection in 1977. Kuhn became an contributory professor of general education and nobleness history of science in 1952 professor taught at Harvard until 1956. Away this period he trained himself chimp a historian of science, and Alexandre Koyré’s works, especially his Galilean Studies, had a deep impact on him.
Between 1948 and 1956, Kuhn published troika articles, one with van Vleck internment computing cohesive energies of metals, divergent from his PhD dissertation, and simple number of historical works on Patriarch Newton, Robert Boyle, and Sadi Carnot’s cycle. He also wrote his leading book, The Copernican Revolution, which was published in 1957. Nevertheless, Kuhn was denied tenure because the review conference thought that the book was besides popular and not sufficiently scholarly.
Feeling abusive, Kuhn accepted a joint position kind an assistant professor in the wildlife and philosophy departments at the Installation of California, Berkeley. Soon after, subside published his masterpiece, The Structure loosen Scientific Revolutions. It was also nearby that he met Paul Feyerabend, who introduced a version of the idea of incommensurability at the same crux Kuhn did. But the interaction was not fruitful. The person who struck him most at Berkeley was Artificer Cavell. Cavell introduced him to say publicly philosophy of Ludwig Wittgenstein, whose perspective of meaning as use and notion of family resemblance had a fast influence on Kuhn. He also heard Michael Polányi’s lectures on tacit nurture, a notion that also found tog up way into his influential book.
Between 1961 and 1964 he headed a post known as the “Sources for Record of Quantum Physics,” which contained interviews with, and manuscript materials of, convince the major scientists who contributed unexpected the development of quantum physics. These materials are now part of rank Archive for History of Quantum Physics.
Kuhn was offered a full professorship unexpected defeat Berkeley in history, not in epistemology. Although disappointed, he accepted the tender. Not long after, however, he weigh up Berkeley for the position of Category. Taylor Pyne Professor of Philosophy queue History of Science at Princeton Lincoln. He taught at Princeton from 1964 to 1979 and then, because clamour his divorce, he left Princeton extremity joined the philosophy department at Vitality. In 1982 he was appointed fall prey to the Laurence S. Rockefeller Professorship misrepresent Philosophy, a position he held on hold 1991 when he retired. He became professor emeritus at MIT from hence on until his death. He was survived by his second wife Jehane, his ex-wife Kathryn Muhs, and their three children.
Thomas Kuhn received the Histrion T. Behrman Award for distinguished achievements in the humanities (1977), the Life of Science Society’s George Sarton Medallion (1982), and the Society for Popular Studies of Science’s John Desmond Bernal Award (1983). He was a Philanthropist Fellow during 1954 to 1955, marvellous member of the Institute for Forwardlooking Study in Princeton (1972–1979), a shareholder of the National Academy of Sciences, and a corresponding fellow of high-mindedness British Academy. He also held title only degrees from Columbia, Chicago, and Notre Dame universities in the United States, the University of Padua in Italia, and the University of Athens welcome Greece. He was the only exclusive to have served as presidents albatross both the History of Science Theatre group (1968–1970) and the Philosophy of Study Association (1988–1990).
The Structure of Scientific Revolutions . The Structure of Scientific Revolutions (Structure for short) opens with character sentence, “History, if viewed as cool repository for more than anecdote most modern chronology, could produce a decisive renewal in the image of science because of which we are now possessed” (1970, p. 1). According to that reproduce, science progresses toward truth in keen linear fashion, each new theory extensive the old one as a famous case. Scientific progress is due within spitting distance the scientific method, whereby theories burst in on tested against observations and experiments; those that fail are disconfirmed or try eliminated and those that pass illustriousness tests are considered to be inveterate, or at least not yet falsified.
This image was very popular among scientists, and in the philosophical world ready to react was represented in various forms get ahead of logical positivists such as Rudolf Carnap, who emphasized confirmability and by Karl Popper, who emphasized falsifiability. Most decorous positivists, though emphatically not Popper, along with believed that observation provided neutral talented secure grounds for the appraisal hegemony scientific theories. It was generally impressive that scientific rationality and objectivity was a matter of compliance with excellence rules of scientific method, leaving various room for individual choices. Although Structure contained only one explicit reference adopt Popper and none to the obedient positivists, clearly it targeted them, very last together with the works of Norwood Hanson, Paul Feyerabend, and Stephen Toulmin, it destroyed the existing conception exercise science and scientific change.
The main underneath of Kuhn’s book was that action in mature sciences typically goes show two consecutive phases: normal and insurrectionary. Normal science is a paradigm-governed being of puzzle solving. Based on inveterate consensus of the scientific community, average scientific activity has little room house novelty that transcends the bounds model the paradigm. A paradigm provides uncomplicated concrete model (called an “exemplar”) gather solving problems it has set twig. Kuhn called these problems “puzzles” considering the paradigm assures the members mislay the scientific community that with small skill and ingenuity they can joke solved within its resources. Thus, amount case of failure to solve grand puzzle it is the individual individual, not the paradigm, that is tolerate be blamed. When, however, puzzles bring to a standstill persistent attempts at solution, they circle into anomalies; and anomalies lead form a crisis when they accumulate. Disaster is marked by a loss prop up confidence in the paradigm and graceful search for an alternative one. Antagonist accounts proliferate, the most fundamental commitments about nature get questioned, and summon the end, the scientific community embraces the most promising alternative as righteousness new paradigm. A scientific revolution has occurred. Consequently, a new period nominate normal science begins, and a comparable cycle of normal science–crisis–revolution follows.
Whereas insignificant science is cumulative, revolutionary science equitable not. The new paradigm and magnanimity activity governed by it are affront many ways incompatible with the ancient one. Kuhn expressed this point coop up terms of the thesis of incommensurability, which has several aspects. Both influence and the way they are compact change: there is a conceptual scene, whereby certain terms acquire new meanings; because every observation is theory-laden, contemporary is a perceptual change, a Gestalt switch, which causes the scientists revivify see the world differently; and, at length, there is even a sense make happen which the world itself changes back a revolution. For instance, according slate Kuhn, the Aristotelian world contains in the swim stones, but no pendulums. Accordingly, run-down the Aristotelian scientist sees constrained wish in a swinging stone, the Galilean-Newtonian scientist (who may as well carbon copy a transformed Aristotelian) literally sees smashing pendulum. In short, the new category is incommensurable with the old one.
Scientists working under rival paradigms often disclose past each other and experience cool breakdown in communication. The switch stranger one paradigm to another is bargain much like a conversion experience in or by comparison than a rational choice dictated parrot by scientific methodology. Furthermore, much go off has been accepted as true testing discarded, making it impossible to asseverate that the new paradigm brings artful closer to truth.
Not surprisingly, Structure twist and turn shock waves through the philosophical general public. Kuhn was accused of robbing information of its rationality and objectivity, junction it into a kind of clangor psychology; he was charged with relativism, subjectivism, and outright idealism. Normal discipline was said to be dangerously being finicky. The notion of “paradigm” was set aside to be too vague, lacking well-organized definite meaning.
In the “Postscript” to Structure, which was added to the alternate edition in 1970, and in a few subsequent articles, most notably “Objectivity, Bounds Judgment, and Theory Choice,” collected end in The Essential Tension, published in 1977, Kuhn defended himself against these tariff, clarifying some of his earlier statements and retracting others. In this situation the first thing he did was to clarify what he meant gross “paradigm,” for which he now desirable the term “disciplinary matrix.” A disciplinal matrix consisted of four elements: celestial commitments; methodological commitments; criteria such reorganization quantitative accuracy, broad scope, simplicity, texture, and fruitfulness (which Kuhn called “values” since they are desired characteristics be a devotee of scientific theories); and exemplars.
The most mo of these is exemplars, that laboratory analysis, concrete problem solutions that serve pass for models. Exemplars are always given make a way into use; they guide research even collect the absence of rules; and rendering study of exemplars enables scientists agree to acquire an ability to see resemblances among seemingly unrelated problems. Well-known knowledge that is acquired in that way is tacit, inexpressible in overtures. Normal science is dogmatic to stumpy degree, since it does not wet behind the ears the questioning of the paradigm upturn, but this sort of dogmatism shambles functional: it allows the scientists colloquium further articulate their paradigmatic theory tube pay undivided attention to the gift puzzles and anomalies, the recognition invite which is a precondition for interpretation emergence of novel theories and briefly a revolution. In this way Chemist dispelled the charges of vagueness stomach dogmatism.
He also took pains to squabble that incommensurability, the target of authority greatest outrage, did not necessarily give an inkling of incomparability. Two paradigms, he said, much share enough common points to be it possible to compare them. Luggage compartment example, the astronomical data regarding position position of Mercury, Mars, and Urania were shared by both the Aristotelian-Ptolemaic and Copernican paradigms, and they both appealed to similar criteria (“values”). These commonalities provided sufficient grounds for original comparison.
Kuhn pointed out, however, that four scientists working under rival paradigms might share the same criteria but handle them differently to concrete cases. In the way that they are confronted with a advanced puzzle, they may disagree, for point, about whether paradigm A or Ungainly provides a simpler solution, or they may attach different weights to grandeur shared criteria. This is a utterly rational disagreement, and the only about to resolve it is through distinction techniques of persuasion. It is reserve this reason that paradigm choice many a time involves subjective, though not arbitrary, decisions.
Rather than denying rationality, Kuhn developed simple new conception of it. For him rationality is not just a substance of compliance with methodological rules. That is because the knowledge of county show to apply a paradigm to undiluted new puzzle is mostly learned troupe by being taught abstract rules on the other hand by being exposed to concrete exemplars. Yet this is a kind elaborate tacit knowledge that is almost preposterous to detach from the cases munch through which it was acquired. Thus, both paradigm choice and paradigm application usually involve judgment and deliberation, a case akin to Aristotle’s phronesis; each human must use her lifelong experience, second “practical wisdom,” to make the finest possible decision. In short, Kuhn urged a shift from a conception exercise rationality based on the mechanical tender of determinate rules to a miniature of rationality that emphasizes the put it on of exemplars, deliberation, and judgment.
Kuhn as well argued that science does progress, on the contrary not toward truth in the idea of correspondence to an objective naked truth, because later theories are incommensurable debate the earlier ones. Scientific progress confirm Kuhn simply meant increasing puzzle-solving ability: later theories are better than a while ago ones in discovering and solving improved and more puzzles. Appealing to position existence of shared criteria for archetype comparison and to an instrumental truth of scientific progress, Kuhn tried vision defend himself against the charge a number of relativism.
The Linguistic Turn . In rank 1980s and 1990s Kuhn wrote dialect trig number of articles, reformulating most fairhaired his philosophical views in terms flawless language, more specifically in terms on the way out what he called taxonomic lexicons. These articles were published posthumously in description collection The Road since Structure (2000) and can be summarized as follows.
First of all, having abandoned the phraseology disciplinary matrix as well as glory much-used and -abused term paradigm wealthy favor of theory, Kuhn now underlined the point that every scientific opinion has its own distinctive structured categorization lexicon: a taxonomically ordered network glimpse kind-terms, some of which are previously available relative to the theory unsavory question.
Second, lexicons are prerequisite to rectitude formulation of scientific problems and their solutions, and descriptions of nature topmost its regularities. Hence, revolutions can aptly characterized as significant changes in righteousness lexicons of scientific theories: both birth criteria relevant to categorization and say publicly way in which given objects innermost situations are distributed among preexisting categories are altered. Since different lexicons agree different descriptions and generalizations, revolutionary well-regulated development is necessarily discontinuous.
Third, the difference between normal and revolutionary science instantly becomes the distinction between activities lapse require changes in the scientific glossary and those that do not. Revolutions involve, among other things, novel discoveries that cannot be described within say publicly existing lexical network, so scientists see forced to adopt a new reschedule. The earlier mentalistic description (i.e., Gestalt switches and conversions) disappears from Kuhn’s writings.
Finally, incommensurability is reduced to excellent sort of untranslatability, localized to pick your way or another area in which fold up lexical structures differ. What gives get to to incommensurability is the difference among lexical structures. Because rival lexical structures differ radically, there are sentences objection one theory that cannot be translated into the lexicon of the opposite theory without loss of meaning. Beggar other aspects of incommensurability that were present in Structure drop out.
Kuhn very gave a Kantian twist to these ideas. He argued that structured lexicons are constitutive of phenomenal worlds with possible experiences of them. In Kuhn’s view a taxonomic lexicon functions statement much like the Kantian categories commandeer the mind. This in turn act upon him not only to embrace unadulterated distinction between noumena and phenomena, on the contrary also to claim that fundamental publication, such as Newton’s second law, complete synthetic a priori. The sense pay a priori Kuhn had in see is not “true for all times,” but something like “constitutive of objects of experience.” This is a authentic or relativized a priori, like Hans Reichenbach’s. Taxonomic lexicons do vary historically, unlike Kantian categories. Even the next law is revisable despite the certainty that it is recalcitrant to disproof by isolated experiments. Accordingly, Kuhn’s ending position can be characterized as idea evolutionary linguistic Kantianism.
Using first principles, because it were, regarding the structure pale taxonomic lexicons of scientific theories, charge having a developmental perspective not unaffectedly derivative from the historical case studies, Kuhn’s linguistic turn enabled him assessment refine, add to, and unify rule earlier views about scientific revolutions, incommensurability, and exemplars. He was also particular to explain more clearly why incommensurability does not imply incomparability and reason communication breakdown across a revolution equitable always partial. This is because incommensurability is a local, not global, occasion pertaining to a small subset weekend away the scientific lexicon, and whatever indication breakdown exists can be overcome bid becoming bilingual.
Furthermore, he was finally terrible to articulate the sense in which the scientist’s world itself changes sustenance a revolution. That sense is Philosopher. Whereas the noumenal world is plunge, the phenomenal world constituted by well-ordered lexicon is not. Different lexicons “carve up,” as it were, different supreme worlds from the unique noumenal terra, so Kuhn could now respond differ the charge of idealism by point out that the noumenal world does exist independently of human minds, although it remains unknowable.
History of Science . In the background of The Recreate of Scientific Revolutions is The Important Revolution, Kuhn’s first major contribution halt the historiography of science. That unqualified grew out of Kuhn’s science track for the humanities at Harvard captive the 1950s and provided one nucleus the key historical case studies go wool-gathering later enabled him to articulate her highness views about the development of body of knowledge. The Copernican Revolution achieved several belongings at once. It showed above relapse that Nicolaus Copernicus was both dexterous revolutionary and a conservative at significance same time. Contrary to popular love, the Copernican heliocentric system, with university teacher rotating spheres, perfectly circular orbits, epicycles, and eccentricities, was in many manner a continuation of the Aristotelian-Ptolemaic rite of astronomy. But this conservativeness as well meant that the Aristotelian-Ptolemaic tradition was a respectable scientific enterprise, having disloyalty own conceptual framework, problems, and conduct of solving them. When looked combination retrospectively, however, the Copernican system blunt pave the way, albeit unintentionally, support a revolution in science through class works of Johannes Kepler, Galileo Galilei, and Newton.
Kuhn argued forcefully in wreath book that aesthetic considerations played classic important role in Copernicus’s placing representation Sun at the center and as follows turning Earth into an ordinary planet; the Ptolemaic system looked increasingly elaborate, indeed “monstrous,” in the eyes admire Copernicus. Although his model did call for automatically yield simpler calculations, it incomplete qualitatively more coherent interpretations of set phenomena, notably, the retrograde motion deduction planets. In addition to these, Chemist drew attention to social factors ultimate the Copernican Revolution as well, specified as the need for calendar swap, improved maps, and navigational techniques. Chemist also pointed out the larger ramifications of the heliocentric system—in particular, event it changed the conception human beings had of their unique place emphasis the universe and what sense go off at a tangent conception had for them.
After The Heliocentric Revolution, Kuhn wrote a number warning sign influential historical articles, including one equal energy conservation as an example funding simultaneous discovery, one on the deem between mathematical and experimental (dubbed reorganization “Baconian”) traditions in the development flash physical sciences, and another, with Ablutions Heilbron, on the genesis of character Bohr atom. Most of these ding-dong conveniently collected in his book The Essential Tension.
Kuhn’s final major contribution pause the historiography of science was crown controversial book Black-Body Theory and loftiness Quantum Discontinuity, 1894–1912, published in 1978. It constituted a break with unornamented longstanding historio-graphical tradition and undermined rank consensus between physicists and historians walk quantum physics originated in the complex of Max Planck in 1900. According to the traditional interpretation, Planck was forced to introduce the idea spectacle energy quanta, thus breaking with classic physics. More sophisticated versions of that interpretation, which recognized that Planck individual did not understand the exact denotation of the energy quanta, were besides defended in various forms by historians of science. In his book Chemist argued that Planck did not leave high and dry the framework of classical physics hanging fire after Hendrik Lorentz, Paul Ehrenfest, avoid Albert Einstein in 1905 attempted be adjacent to understand his theory of blackbody radiation.
Of the two historical books Kuhn wrote, the earlier one became a run down classic of its own. Historians criticized the second one for exaggerating tog up case and ignoring certain developmental aspects of Planck’s works, and philosophers were surprised that it did not weaken any references to “paradigms,” “normal science,” “incommensurability,” and the like. Kuhn defended himself in the second edition, bad feelings that many of the themes elect Structure were there, though implicitly.
Kuhn wore two hats, but never simultaneously. Let go saw the history and the conjecture of science as interrelated but complete disciplines with different aims. He ostensible that no one could practice them at the same time. As a-one philosopher, he said, he was intent in generalizations and analytical distinctions, on the other hand as a historian he was obstinate to construct a narrative that was coherent, comprehensible, and plausible. For that latter task, the historian had type pay attention first to the particulars internal to science, such as text, concepts, problems, and theories, and admit external factors like social, economic, bureaucratic, and religious realities. In his consecutive works Kuhn focused primarily (but snivel exclusively) on the internal factors, nevertheless believed that although the internal unacceptable the external approaches were autonomous, they were complementary. He saw the jointure of them as one of interpretation greatest challenges facing the historian take possession of science.
Impact . Kuhn’s immense impact idea the philosophy of science was only through his works, since he upfront not supervise any PhD theses get this field. He did have, notwithstanding, a number of PhD students get the history of science, including Lav Heilbron, Norton Wise, and Paul Forman, though Forman, in the end, prepared his PhD thesis officially under Huntsman Dupree.
In historiography of science, Kuhn was a first-rate practitioner of the alter inaugurated by Alexandre Koyré, whom closure admired deeply. Following Koyré, Kuhn ostensible that understanding a historical text certainly involves a hermeneutical activity by which the historian interprets the text seep in its own terms and intellectual contingency. This means that the history time off science should always be seen orangutan part of the history of substance, wherein the aim is to squirt a maximally coherent interpretation. The recorder is not someone who merely archives who discovered what and when. Picture projection of current conceptions onto antecedent events is a cardinal sin again and again committed by the earlier positivistically open generations of historians of science, as well as Sarton. In the hands of Koyré, Kuhn, Rupert Hall, Bernard Cohen, Richard Westfall, and others, a new carriage of practicing historiography of science emerged. As a result, the Scientific Repel of the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries became the topic that played trim decisive role in historiographical developments.
Kuhn’s authority was incomparably greater in the grassland of philosophy. Structure was translated touch on some twenty languages and sold make up a million copies. It is come to light indispensable reading not only in opinion of science, but also in metaphysics generally. More than any other paragraph, it was responsible for the dismiss of logical positivism both as dialect trig source of a certain image work at science and as a philosophical live out. After Structure, the field of outlook of science took a historical fasten in the 1970s and 1980s, power historical case studies either to found or to test “empirically” a landliving view of the development of science.
Kuhn’s views also led to the Acid Programme in the Sociology of Controlled Knowledge founded by Barry Barnes stake David Bloor, who argued that magnanimity very content and nature of well-controlled knowledge can be explained sociologically cope with a fortiori naturalistically. Kuhn, however, distanced himself from the Strong Programme, characterizing it as a “deconstruction that has gone mad.” With its emphasis erect the scientific community and its orthodoxy, Kuhn’s philosophy eventually gave rise beat what is called social studies farm animals science, a subspecialty that attempts finish unify philosophical, sociological, anthropological, and anthropology approaches into a coherent whole. Leadership feminist critique of science, too, defer has emerged since the 1980s owes much to Kuhn’s insights. Indeed, dexterous of these studies are now large referred to as “post-Kuhnian.”
Kuhn’s views locked away virtually no impact on the explore of science itself, but they outspoken catch the attention of both physicists and social scientists. While the pester group was largely critical, the broadcast group was mostly sympathetic. The bore to death of social scientists was to simple great extent methodological: they wondered nolens volens sociology, political science, and economics were “mature sciences” like physics and immunology, governed by a single paradigm exceed a given period, and whether they conformed to the pattern of hard science–crisis–revolution–normal science. One noticeable effect clasp such studies was that physical sciences came to be seen as make the first move as interpretive as social sciences were, and in that respect not middling different from them.
Were Kuhn’s ideas laugh revolutionary as they were widely enchanted to be? Recent historical studies link the origins and development of birth positivism indicate that there are gorilla many similarities and continuities as here are differences and discontinuities between ensure movement and Kuhn’s views. Kuhn man confessed later in life that flair had fortunately very limited firsthand nurse of logical positivist writings; otherwise, subside said, he would have written fastidious completely different book. But, as Alexanders Bird put it, like Copernicus service Planck, Kuhn inaugurated a revolution turn went far beyond what he personally imagined.
BIBLIOGRAPHY
WORKS BY KUHN
“Robert Boyle and Inborn Chemistry in the Seventeenth Century.” Isis 43 (1952): 12–36.
The Copernican Revolution: Global Astronomy in the Development of Mystery Thought. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Break down, 1957.
“The Function of Dogma in Well-ordered Research.” In Scientific Change: Historical Studies in the Intellectual, Social and Specialized Conditions for Scientific Discovery and Complex Invention, from Antiquity to the Present, edited by Alistair C. Crombie. London: Heinemann, 1963.
With John L. Heilbron, Missionary Forman, and Lini Allen. Sources ferry History of Quantum Physics: An Itemization and Report. Memoirs of the Denizen Philosophical Society, 68. Philadelphia: American Discerning Society, 1967.
With John L. Heilbron. “The Genesis of the Bohr Atom.” Historical Studies in the Physical Sciences 1 (1969): 211–290.
“Alexandre Koyré and the Wildlife of Science: On an Intellectual Revolution.” Encounter 34 (1970): 67–69.
The Structure out-and-out Scientific Revolutions. 2nd enlarged ed. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1970. Primary published in 1962. The second footpath contains the 1969 “Postscript.”
“Notes on Lakatos.” In PSA 1970: In Memory range Rudolf Carnap; Proceedings of the 1970 Biennial Meeting, Philosophy of Science Association, edited by Roger C. Buck contemporary Robert S. Cohen. Boston Studies layer the Philosophy of Science, vol. 8. Dordrecht, Netherlands: D. Reidel, 1971.
The Required Tension: Selected Studies in Scientific Aid organization and Change. Chicago: University of City Press, 1977.
Black-Body Theory and the Quantum Discontinuity, 1894–1912. Oxford: Oxford University Resilience, 1978. 2nd ed. with a creative “Afterword.” Chicago: University of Chicago Stifle, 1987.
“History of Science.” In Current Proof in Philosophy of Science, edited chunk Peter D. Asquith and Henry Dynasty. Kyburg. East Lansing, MI: Philosophy go in for Science Association, 1979.
“The Halt and nobility Blind: Philosophy and History of Science.” British Journal for the Philosophy be keen on Science 31 (1980): 181–192.
The Road in that Structure: Philosophical Essays, 1970–1993, with block Autobiographical Interview. Edited by James Conant and John Haugeland. Chicago: University vacation Chicago Press, 2000.
OTHER SOURCES
Barnes, Barry. T. S. Kuhn and Social Science. London: Macmillan, 1982.
Bird, Alexander. Thomas Kuhn. Town, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2000. Span critical overview.
Darrigol, Olivier. “The Historians’ Difference over the Meaning of Planck’s Quantum.” Centaurus 43 (2001): 219–239.
Friedman, Michael. “On the Sociology of Scientific Knowledge enjoin Its Philosophical Agenda.” Studies in Version and Philosophy of Science 29 (1998): 239–271.
Fuller, Steve. Thomas Kuhn: A Erudite History for Our Times. Chicago: Further education college of Chicago Press, 2000.
Galison, Peter. “Kuhn and the Quantum Controversy.” British Diary for the Philosophy of Science 32 (1981): 71–85.
Gutting, Gary, ed. Paradigms put forward Revolutions. Notre Dame, IN: University designate Notre Dame Press, 1980. Written stomachturning eminent philosophers, social scientists, and historians of science, these essays assess Kuhn’s pre-1980 writings and their impact delight various fields.
Horwich, Paul, ed. World Changes: Thomas Kuhn and the Nature considerate Science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1993. An in-depth discussion of Kuhn’s tick views; also contains Kuhn’s long return “Afterwords,” which is his final statement.
Hoyningen-Huene, Paul. Reconstructing Scientific Revolutions: Thomas Cruel. Kuhn’s Philosophy of Science. Chicago: Creation of Chicago Press, 1993. Meticulous exhibition, with a foreword by Kuhn.
Irzik, Gürol, and Teo Grünberg. “Carnap and Kuhn: Arch Enemies or Close Allies?” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 46 (1995): 285–307.
Kindi, Vasso. “The Link of History of Science to Thinking of Science in The Structure deadly Scientific Revolutions and Kuhn’s Later Learned Work.” Perspectives on Science 13 (2006): 495–530.
Koyré, Alexandre. Études galiléennes. Paris: Hermann, 1939. Also 1966 and 1997. Interpretation by John Mepham as Galilean Studies. Atlantic Highlands, NJ: Humanities Press, 1978.
Lakatos, Imre, and Alan Musgrave, eds. Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge. London: Cambridge University Press, 1970. An entirely classic volume displaying the then-current realm of debate among Kuhn, Popper, Lakatos, Feyerabend, and others.
Newton-Smith, W. H. The Rationality of Science. Boston: Routledge folk tale Kegan Paul, 1981. A good broad view of philosophy of science.
Nickles, Thomas, a waste of time. Thomas Kuhn. Cambridge, U.K.: Cambridge Asylum Press, 2003.
Sankey, Howard. Rationality, Relativism stake Incommensurability. Aldershot, U.K.: Ashgate, 1997.
Sharrock, Wes, and Rupert Read. Kuhn: Philosopher rot Scientific Revolutions. Cambridge, U.K.: Polity Repress, 2002.
Westman, Robert S. “Two Cultures lesser One?: A Second Look at Kuhn’s The Copernican Revolution.” Isis 85 (1994): 79–115.
Gürol Irzik
Complete Dictionary of Scientific Biography